-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 22
/
fggroups.tex
971 lines (905 loc) · 45.6 KB
/
fggroups.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
\chapter{Group presentations}
\label{ch:fggroups}
\section{Brief overview of the chapter}
\label{sec:fggroups-overview}
TODO:
\begin{itemize}
\item Make a separate chapter on combinatorics? Actions and Burnside and counting colorings?
\item Cayley actions: $G$ acts on $\Gamma(G,S)$: Action on vertices is the left action of $G$ on itself: $t \mapsto (t=_{\BG} \pt)$, on vertices, for $s : S$, have edge $t = \pt$ to $t = \pt$
\item Recall universal property of free groups: If we have a map $\varphi : S \to H$, then we get a homomorphism $\bar\varphi : F(S) \to H$, represented by $BF(S) \to_\pt \BH$ defined by induction, sending $\pt$ to $\pt$ and $s$ to $\varphi(s)$.
\item define different types of graphs ($S$-digraphs, $\tilde S$-graphs,
(partial) functional graphs, graph homomorphisms, quotients of graphs)
\item define (left/right) Cayley graphs of f.g.~groups
-- $\Aut(\Gamma_G) = G$ (include $\alpha : F(S) \to G$ in notation?)
-- Cayley graphs are vertex transitive
\item Cayley graphs and products, semi-direct products, homomorphisms
\item Some isomorphisms involving semi-direct products
-- Exceptional automorphism of $\Sigma_6$:
-- Exotic map $\Sigma_5 \to \Sigma_6$.
(Conjugation action of $\Sigma_5$ on $6$ $5$-Sylow subgroups.)
A set bundle $X : \BSigma_6 \to \BSigma_6$.
\item \url{https://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/six.html}
Relating $\Sigma_6$ to the icosahedron.
The icosahedron has $6$ axes. Two axes determines a golden rectangle (also known as a \emph{duad},\footnote{%
These names come from Sylvester.}
so there are $15$ such. A symmetry of the icosahedron can be described
by knowing where a fixed rectangle goes, and a symmetry of that rectangle.
Picking three rectangles not sharing a diagonal gives a \emph{syntheme}:
three golden rectangles whose vertices make up the icosahedron.
Some synthemes (known as \emph{true crosses}
have the rectangles orthogonal to each other, as in
\cref{fig:true-cross}.
Fact: The symmetries of the icosahedron form the alternating symmetries of the $5$ true crosses.
Of course, we get an action on the $6$ axes, thus a homomorphism $\constant{A}_5 \to \Sigma_6$.
Every golden rectangle lies in one true cross and two skew crosses.
The combinatorics of duads, synthemes, and synthematic totals are illustrated
in the Cremona-Richardson configuration and the resulting Tutte-Coxeter graph.
The automorphism group of the latter is in fact $\Aut(\Sigma_6)$.
If we color the vertices according to duad/syntheme, we get $\Sigma_6$ itself.
\begin{marginfigure}
\tdplotsetmaincoords{45}{135}
\begin{tikzpicture}[tdplot_main_coords,scale=1.1]
\begin{scope}[opacity=0.6]
\draw (-1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803);
\draw (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (-0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803);
\draw (-1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.61803, -0.00000, -1.00000);
\draw (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803);
\draw (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (-1.00000, -1.61803, -0.00000);
\draw (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803);
\draw (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000);
\draw (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803);
\fill[gray] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill[casblue] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 0.00000, -1.61803) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill[casred] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (0.00000, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- cycle;
\draw (0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (-1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803);
\draw (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000);
\fill[casred] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (0.00000, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- cycle;
\fill[casblue] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 0.00000, -1.61803) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill[gray] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\draw (0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000);
\draw (1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000);
\draw (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803);
\fill[casred] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (0.00000, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- cycle;
\fill[gray] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill[casblue] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 0.00000, 1.61803) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\draw (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000);
\draw (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803);
\fill[gray] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill[casblue] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 0.00000, 1.61803) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill[casred] (0.00000, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, 0.00000) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (0.00000, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- cycle;
\draw (0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000);
\draw (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803);
\draw (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000);
\draw (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000);
\draw (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000);
\draw (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000);
\draw (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000);
\end{scope}
\end{tikzpicture}
\caption{Icosahedron with an inscribed true cross}
\label{fig:true-cross}
\end{marginfigure}
\item define (left/right) presentation complex of group presentation
\item define Stallings folding
\item deduce Nielsen--Schreier and Nielsen basis
\item deduce algorithms for generalized word problem, conjugation, etc.
\item deduce Howson's theorem
\item think about 2-cell replacement for folding; better proofs in HoTT?
\item move decidability results to main flow
\item include undecidability of word problem in general
-- doesn't depend on presentation (for classes closed under inverse images of monoid homomorphisms)
\item describe $F(S)/H$ in the case where $H$ has infinite index
\item describe normal closure of $R$ in $F(S)$ -- still f.g.? -- get Cayley graph of $F(S)/\langle R\rangle$. -- Todd-Coxeter algorithm?
\item in good cases we can recognize $\mathcal{S}(R)$ as a ``fundamental domain'' in Cayley graph of $\langle S\mid R\rangle$.
\end{itemize}
\begin{remark}
In this chapter, we use letters from the
beginning of the alphabet $a,b,c,\dots$
to denote generators,
and we use the corresponding capital letters
$A,B,C$ to denote their inverses,
so, e.g., $aA=Aa=1$.
This cleans up the notational clutter significantly.
\end{remark}
Do we fix $S$, a finite set $S=\{a,b,\ldots\}$?
Mostly $F$ will denote the free group on $S$.
And for almost all examples, we take $S = \{a,b\}$.
\section{Graphs and Cayley graphs}
\label{sec:cayley-graphs}
We have seen in the previous chapter how cyclic groups
(those generated by a single generator)
have neatly described types of torsors.
Indeed, $\BCG_n \jdeq \Cyc_n$, where $\Cyc_n$ is the type of $n$-cycles,
and the classifying type of the integers, $\B\ZZ\jdeq\Sc$, \ie the circle,
is equivalent to the type of infinite cycles, $\Cyc_0$.
In \cref{cha:circle}, we defined the types of (finite or infinite)
cycles as certain components of $\sum_{X:\UU}(X\eqto X)$,
but we can equivalently consider components of $\sum_{X:\UU}(X\to X)$,
since the former is a subtype of the latter.
By thinking of functions in terms of their graphs,
we might as well look at components of $\sum_{X:\UU}(X \to X \to \UU)$.
In this section we shall generalize this story
to groups $G$ generated by a
(finite or just decidable)
set of generators $S$.
First recall from Cayley's \cref{lem:allgpsarepermutationgps}
that any group $G$ can be realized as a subgroup of the permutation group
on the underlying set of symmetries in $G$, $\USymG$.
In this description, a $G$-shape is a set $X$ equipped
a $G$-action that defines a $G$-torsor,
which in turn can be expressed as the structure of a map $\alpha:\USymG \to X \to X$
satisfying certain properties.
It may happen that already $\alpha$ restricted to a subset $S$ of $\USymG$
suffices to specify the action.
In that case we say that $S$ generates $G$, though we'll take the following
as the official definition.
\begin{definition}\label{def:gens-gp}
Let $G$ be a group and $S$ be a subset of $\USymG$, given by an inclusion
$\iota : S \to \USymG$. We say that \emph{$S$ generates $G$} if the induced
homomorphism from the free group on $S$,
\[
\FG_S \to G,
\]
is an epimorphism.
\end{definition}
\begin{lemma}\label{lem:gens-gp-iff}
Let $G$ be a group
and $\iota : S \to \USymG$ an inclusion of a subset of the elements of $G$.
Then $S$ generates $G$ if and only if the map
\[
\rho_S : \BG \to \sum_{X:\UU}(S \to X \to X) ,
\quad
\rho_S(t) \defeq \bigl(t \eqto \sh_G, s \mapsto \iota(s) \cdot \blank\bigr)
\]
is an embedding.\footnote{We use $t \eqto \sh_G$ rather than the equivalent
$\sh_G \eqto t$ in order to conform to the representation from Cayley's theorem.}
\end{lemma}
In this case, then, $G$ can be identified with the automorphism group of $\rho_S(\sh_G)$
in the type $\sum_{X:\UU}(S \to X \to X)$, or even in the larger type (of which it's a subtype), $\sum_{X:\UU}(S \to X \to X \to \UU)$.
\tikzset{vertex/.style={circle,fill=black,inner sep=0pt,minimum size=4pt}}
\tikzset{gena/.style={draw=casblue,-stealth}}
\tikzset{genb/.style={draw=casred,-stealth}}
\begin{figure}
\begin{sidecaption}%
{Cayley graph for {$\protect\SG_3$} with respect to $S = \{(1\;2),(2\;3)\}$.}[fig:cayley-s3]
\centering
\begin{tikzpicture}
\pgfmathsetmacro{\len}{2}
\node[vertex,label=30:$(1\;3)$] (n13) at (30:\len) {};
\node[vertex,label=90:$(1\;3\;2)$] (n132) at (90:\len) {};
\node[vertex,label=150:$(1\;2)$] (n12) at (150:\len) {};
\node[vertex,label=210:$e$] (ne) at (210:\len) {};
\node[vertex,label=270:$(2\;3)$] (n23) at (270:\len) {};
\node[vertex,label=330:$(1\;2\;3)$] (n123) at (330:\len) {};
\begin{scope}[every to/.style={bend left=22}]
% generator a is (12)
\draw[gena] (ne) to (n12);
\draw[gena] (n12) to (ne);
\draw[gena] (n13) to (n132);
\draw[gena] (n132) to (n13);
\draw[gena] (n123) to (n23);
\draw[gena] (n23) to (n123);
% generator b is (23)
\draw[genb] (ne) to (n23);
\draw[genb] (n23) to (ne);
\draw[genb] (n13) to (n123);
\draw[genb] (n123) to (n13);
\draw[genb] (n12) to (n132);
\draw[genb] (n132) to (n12);
\end{scope}
\end{tikzpicture}
\end{sidecaption}
\end{figure}
Also note that $S$ generates $G$ if and only if the map on elements
$\UFG_S \to \USymG$ is surjective, meaning every element of $G$ can be expressed
as a product of the letters in a (reduced) word from $\mathcal R_S$, interpreted
according to the inclusion of $S$ into $\USymG$.
This is the case for example for $S$ consisting of the transpositions
$(1\;2)$, $(2\;3)$ in $\SG_3$, as illustrated in~\cref{fig:cayley-s3},
where the \textcolor{casblue}{blue} color represents $(1\;2)$
and the \textcolor{casred}{red} color represents $(2\;3)$.
Before we give the proof of~\cref{lem:gens-gp-iff}, let us study these types more closely.
\begin{definition}
An $S$-labeled graph is an element $(V,E)$ of the type
$\sum_{V:\UU}(S \to V \to V \to \UU)$.%
\index{graph!labeled}
The first component $V$ is called the type of \emph{vertices} of the graph,
and the type $E(s,x,y)$ is called the type of $s$-colored \emph{edges}
from $x$ (the source) to $y$ (the target).
\end{definition}
If for every vertex $x:V$ and every color $s:S$ there is unique $s$-colored edge out of $x$, \ie the type $\sum_{y:V}E(s,x,y)$ is contractible, then we say that the graph
is \emph{functional}. This means that the graph lives in the subtype $\sum_{V:\UU}(S \to V \to V)$,
as is the case for the graph $\rho_S(\sh_G)$ for a group $G$.
This graph is called the Cayley graph of $G$ with respect to the set $S$:
\begin{definition}\label{def:cayley-graph}
The \emph{Cayley graph}\index{graph!Cayley graph}
of a group $G$ with respect to a generating subset $S$
is the graph $\Cay(G;S)$\glossary(Cay){$\protect\Cay(G;S)$}{Cayley graph of a group $G$
with respect to $S$}
is the $S$-colored graph with vertices $\USymG$
and edges $S \times \USymG$ where the edge $(s,g)$ has source $g$, target $sg$,
and color $s$.
\end{definition}
Convince yourself that this is really an equivalent description of $\rho_S(\sh_G)$
considered as an $S$-colored graph.
If $S$ is contractible (so there's only one color), then we just say \emph{graph},
and then we simplify the type of edges to $V \to V \to \UU$.
Of course, every $S$-labeled graph $(V,E)$ gives rise to such an unlabeled label
by summing over the colors, \ie the type of edges from $x$ to $y$ in this graph
is $\sum_{s:S}E(s,x,y)$.
Another way to represent a graph is to sum over all the sources and targets (and colors),
via~\cref{lem:typefamiliesandfibrations},
\ie as a tuple $(V,E,s,t,c)$, where $V:\UU$ is the type of vertices,
$E$ is the (total) type of edges,
$s,t : E \to V$ give the source and target of an edge,
while $c: E \to S$ gives the color (if we're talking about $S$-colored graphs).
In this description, to get the unlabeled graph we simply drop the last component.
Every graph $(V,E)$ (and thus every labeled graph) gives rise to a type
by ``gluing the edges to the vertices'' defined as follows.
\begin{definition}
Fix an unlabeled graph $(V,E)$. The \emph{graph quotient}\footnote{%
If the graph is represented by source and target maps
$s,t: E \rightrightarrows V$, then the graph quotient is
also called the \emph{coequalizer} of $s$ and $t$.} $V/E$ is
the higher inductive type with constructors:
\begin{enumerate}
\item For every vertex $x : V$ a point $[x] : V/E$.
\item For every edge $e : E(x,y)$ an identification $\qedge_e : [x] \eqto [y]$.
\end{enumerate}
Let $A(z)$ be a type for every element $z:V/E$. The induction principle
for $V/E$ states that, in order to define an element of $A(z)$ for every $z:V/E$,
it suffices to give elements $a_x : A([x])$ for every vertex $x:V$
together with
identifications $q_e : \pathover{a_x}{A}{\qedge_e}{a_y}$
for every $e:E(x,y)$.
The function $f$ thus defined satisfies $f([x])\jdeq a_x$ for $x:V$
and we are provided identifications $\apd{f}(\qedge_e)\eqto q_e$ for each $e:E(x,y)$.
\end{definition}
\begin{remark}
Note the similarity with the classifying type of a free group,
\cf~\cref{def:bfree}. Indeed, if we form the (unlabeled!)
graph $(\bn 1,S)$
on one vertex with $S$ edges, then $\bn 1/S$ is essentially the same as $\BFG_S$.
\end{remark}
\begin{xca}
An equivalence relation $R : A \to A \to \Prop$ on a set $A$
can be regarded as a graph $(A,R)$.
Construct an equivalence between set truncation of the graph quotient $\Trunc{A/R}_0$
and the set quotient $A/R$ from~\cref{def:quotient-set} in this case.
(So in the world of sets, the two notations agree.)
\end{xca}
While we're building up to the proof of~\cref{lem:gens-gp-iff} we need
a description of a sum type over a graph quotient.
By the above remark, this applies also to sum types over $\BFG_S$.
\begin{construction}\label{def:graph-quotient-flattening}
Given a graph $(V,E)$ and a family of types $X : V/E \to \UU$.
Define $V' \defeq \sum_{v:V}X([v])$ and
$E'((v,x),(w,y)) \defeq \sum_{e:E(v,w)}\pathover{x}{X}{\qedge_e}{y}$.
Then we have an equivalence\index{flattening construction}\footnote{%
This is often called the \emph{flattening construction} (or flattening lemma),
as it ``flattens'' a sum over a graph quotient into a single graph quotient.}
\[
\flt : \Bigl(\sum_{z:V/E}X(z)\Bigr) \equivto V'/E'
\]
\end{construction}
\begin{implementation}{def:graph-quotient-flattening}
We define functions $\varphi : V'/E' \to \sum_{z:V/E}X(z)$
and $\psi : \prod_{z:V/E}\bigl(X(z) \to V'/E'\bigr)$
using the induction principles:
\begin{alignat*}2
\varphi([(v,x)]) &\defeq ([v],x) &\quad
\tilde\psi([v]) &\defeq (x \mapsto [(v,x)]) \\
\ap\varphi(\qedge_{(e,q)}) &\defis \pathpair{\qedge_e}{q} &\quad
\apd{\tilde\psi}(\qedge_e) &\defis h,
\end{alignat*}
where we need to construct\marginnote{%
\begin{tikzcd}[column sep=small,ampersand replacement=\&]
X([v]) \ar[rr,"{\trp[X]{\qedge_e}}","\simeq"']\ar[dr,"{\psi([v])}"']
\& \& X([w]) \ar[dl,"{\psi([w])}"] \\
\& V'/E' \&
\end{tikzcd}}
$h : \pathover{(x \mapsto [(v,x)])}{z \mapsto X(z) \to V'/E'}{\qedge_e}
{(y \mapsto [(w,y)])}$ for all $e : E(v,w)$.
By transporting in families of functions,
it suffices to give an identification
$[(v,x)] \eqto [(w,\trp[X]{\qedge_e}(x))]$ for all $x : X([v])$.
We get this as the identification constructor $\qedge_{(e,q)}$ for $V'/E'$,
where $q: \pathover{x}{X}{\qedge_e}{\trp[X]{\qedge_e}(x)}$
is the identification over $\qedge_e$ corresponding
to the reflexivity identification at
$\trp[X]{\qedge_e}(x)$ via~\cref{def:pathover-trp}.
\end{implementation}
\begin{xca}
Complete the implementation by giving identifications $\psi\circ\phi\eqto\id$
and $\phi\circ\psi\eqto\id$, where $\psi : \bigl(\sum_{z:V/E}X(z)\bigr) \to V'/E'$
is defined by $\psi((z,x)) \defeq \tilde\psi(z)(x)$.
\end{xca}
Later on we'll need also need the following results about graph quotients.
\begin{xca}\label{xca:graph-quotient-in-steps}
Suppose the edges $E$ of a graph $(V,E)$ are expressed as a binary sum $E_0 \amalg E_1$.
(Here, it doesn't matter whether $E$ is expressed as a type family $E : V \to V \to \UU$,
in which case we have a family of equivalences $E(v,w) \equivto E_0(v,w) \amalg E_1(v,w)$,
or $E$ is the total type of edges.)
Then we can obtain the graph quotient $V/E$ by first gluing in the edges from $E_0$,
and then gluing in the edges from $E_1$ to the resulting type $V/E_0$.
Using the description of graphs with a total type of edges $E \equivto E_0 \amalg E_1$,
we have corresponding source and target maps expressed as compositions:
\[
E_1 \hookrightarrow E_0\amalg E_1 \equivto E \rightrightarrows V \to V/E_0.
\]
Construct an equivalence $V/E \equivto V/(E_0 \amalg E_1) \equivto (V/E_0)/E_1$.
\end{xca}
\begin{xca}\label{xca:graph-quotient-whisker}
Suppose we have any type $X$ with an element $x:X$.
We can form a graph $(X\amalg\bn 1,\bn 1)$ with vertex type $X\amalg\bn 1$
and a single edge from $\inl x$ to $\inr 0$.
Construct an equivalence $X \equivto (X\amalg\bn 1)/\bn 1$.\footnote{%
This equivalence can be visualized as follows, where $X$ ``grows a whisker''
along the single edge.\\
\begin{tikzpicture}
\draw (0,0) ellipse (1 and 1.2);
\node (X) at (0,1.5) {$X$};
\node (t) at (1.7,0.6) {$\bn 1$};
\node[dot,label=below:$x$] (x) at (.6,0.3) {};
\node[dot] (pt) at (1.5,.4) {};
\draw[->,bend left] (x) -- (pt) {};
\end{tikzpicture}}
\end{xca}
\section{Examples}
\label{sec:fg-examples}
\begin{proof}[Proof of~\cref{lem:gens-gp-iff}]
TBD (perhaps put in graph quotients first)
\end{proof}
\begin{figure}
\begin{sidecaption}%
{Cayley graph for $A_5$ with respect to $S = \{a,b\}$,
where $a$ is a $1/5$-rotation about a vertex and
$b$ is a $1/2$-rotation about an edge in an icosahedron.}[fig:cayley-a5]
\centering
\tdplotsetmaincoords{45}{135}
\begin{tikzpicture}[tdplot_main_coords,scale=2]
% cayley icosahedron
\begin{scope}[fill=casblue,opacity=.2]
\fill (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (-0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (-0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- cycle;
\fill (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (-0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (-0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (1.61803, -0.00000, 1.00000) -- (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (0.00000, 1.00000, 1.61803) -- (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (-0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (-1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (1.61803, -0.00000, 1.00000) -- (1.00000, 1.61803, -0.00000) -- (1.61803, -0.00000, -1.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (-0.00000, -1.00000, 1.61803) -- (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.00000, 1.61803, -0.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803) -- cycle;
\fill (-1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (-1.00000, -1.61803, -0.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (1.61803, 0.00000, 1.00000) -- (1.61803, -0.00000, -1.00000) -- (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (-1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.00000, -1.61803, -0.00000) -- (-0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803) -- cycle;
\fill (-1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803) -- cycle;
\fill (1.00000, 1.61803, 0.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803) -- (1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- cycle;
\fill (1.00000, -1.61803, 0.00000) -- (1.61803, -0.00000, -1.00000) -- (-0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803) -- cycle;
\fill (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (-1.00000, -1.61803, -0.00000) -- (-0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803) -- cycle;
\fill (1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803) -- cycle;
\fill (0.00000, 1.00000, -1.61803) -- (-1.61803, 0.00000, -1.00000) -- (0.00000, -1.00000, -1.61803) -- cycle;
\end{scope}
\node[vertex] (n) at (0.00000, 0.50000, 1.61803) {};
\node[vertex] (na) at (0.40451, 0.75000, 1.46353) {};
\node[vertex] (nb) at (-0.00000, -0.50000, 1.61803) {};
\node[vertex] (nA) at (-0.40451, 0.75000, 1.46353) {};
\node[vertex] (naa) at (0.25000, 1.15451, 1.21353) {};
\node[vertex] (nba) at (-0.40451, -0.75000, 1.46353) {};
\node[vertex] (nab) at (1.21353, 0.25000, 1.15451) {};
\node[vertex] (nAb) at (-1.21353, 0.25000, 1.15451) {};
\node[vertex] (nbA) at (0.40451, -0.75000, 1.46353) {};
\node[vertex] (nAA) at (-0.25000, 1.15451, 1.21353) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaa) at (-0.25000, -1.15451, 1.21353) {};
\node[vertex] (naba) at (1.21353, -0.25000, 1.15451) {};
\node[vertex] (nAba) at (-1.46353, 0.40451, 0.75000) {};
\node[vertex] (naab) at (0.75000, 1.46353, 0.40451) {};
\node[vertex] (nbab) at (-1.21353, -0.25000, 1.15451) {};
\node[vertex] (nAAb) at (-0.75000, 1.46353, 0.40451) {};
\node[vertex] (nabA) at (1.46353, 0.40451, 0.75000) {};
\node[vertex] (nbAA) at (0.25000, -1.15451, 1.21353) {};
\node[vertex] (nabaa) at (1.46353, -0.40451, 0.75000) {};
\node[vertex] (nAbaa) at (-1.61803, 0.00000, 0.50000) {};
\node[vertex] (naaba) at (1.15451, 1.21353, 0.25000) {};
\node[vertex] (nAAba) at (-0.50000, 1.61803, 0.00000) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaab) at (-0.75000, -1.46353, 0.40451) {};
\node[vertex] (nAbab) at (-1.15451, 1.21353, 0.25000) {};
\node[vertex] (nbAAb) at (0.75000, -1.46353, 0.40451) {};
\node[vertex] (naabA) at (0.50000, 1.61803, 0.00000) {};
\node[vertex] (nbabA) at (-1.46353, -0.40451, 0.75000) {};
\node[vertex] (nabAA) at (1.61803, -0.00000, 0.50000) {};
\node[vertex] (naabaa) at (1.15451, 1.21353, -0.25000) {};
\node[vertex] (nAAbaa) at (-0.75000, 1.46353, -0.40451) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaaba) at (-1.15451, -1.21353, 0.25000) {};
\node[vertex] (nbAAba) at (0.50000, -1.61803, 0.00000) {};
\node[vertex] (nabaab) at (1.15451, -1.21353, 0.25000) {};
\node[vertex] (nAbaab) at (-1.61803, 0.00000, -0.50000) {};
\node[vertex] (nabAAb) at (1.61803, -0.00000, -0.50000) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaabA) at (-0.50000, -1.61803, 0.00000) {};
\node[vertex] (nAbabA) at (-1.15451, 1.21353, -0.25000) {};
\node[vertex] (naabAA) at (0.75000, 1.46353, -0.40451) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaabaa) at (-1.15451, -1.21353, -0.25000) {};
\node[vertex] (nbAAbaa) at (0.75000, -1.46353, -0.40451) {};
\node[vertex] (nAbaaba) at (-1.46353, 0.40451, -0.75000) {};
\node[vertex] (nabAAba) at (1.46353, -0.40451, -0.75000) {};
\node[vertex] (naabaab) at (1.46353, 0.40451, -0.75000) {};
\node[vertex] (nAAbaab) at (-0.25000, 1.15451, -1.21353) {};
\node[vertex] (naabAAb) at (0.25000, 1.15451, -1.21353) {};
\node[vertex] (nabaabA) at (1.15451, -1.21353, -0.25000) {};
\node[vertex] (nAbaabA) at (-1.46353, -0.40451, -0.75000) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaabAA) at (-0.75000, -1.46353, -0.40451) {};
\node[vertex] (nAbaabaa) at (-1.21353, 0.25000, -1.15451) {};
\node[vertex] (nabAAbaa) at (1.21353, -0.25000, -1.15451) {};
\node[vertex] (naabAAba) at (0.40451, 0.75000, -1.46353) {};
\node[vertex] (nbAAbaab) at (0.25000, -1.15451, -1.21353) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaabAAb) at (-0.25000, -1.15451, -1.21353) {};
\node[vertex] (naabaabA) at (1.21353, 0.25000, -1.15451) {};
\node[vertex] (nAAbaabA) at (-0.40451, 0.75000, -1.46353) {};
\node[vertex] (nAbaabAA) at (-1.21353, -0.25000, -1.15451) {};
\node[vertex] (naabAAbaa) at (0.00000, 0.50000, -1.61803) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaabAAba) at (-0.40451, -0.75000, -1.46353) {};
\node[vertex] (nabAAbaab) at (0.40451, -0.75000, -1.46353) {};
\node[vertex] (nbaabAAbaa) at (-0.00000, -0.50000, -1.61803) {};
\draw[gena] (n) -- (nA);
\draw[genb] (n) -- (nb);
\draw[gena] (na) -- (n);
\draw[genb] (na) -- (nab);
\draw[gena] (nb) -- (nbA);
\draw[genb] (nb) -- (n);
\draw[gena] (nA) -- (nAA);
\draw[genb] (nA) -- (nAb);
\draw[gena] (naa) -- (na);
\draw[genb] (naa) -- (naab);
\draw[gena] (nba) -- (nb);
\draw[genb] (nba) -- (nbab);
\draw[gena] (nab) -- (nabA);
\draw[genb] (nab) -- (na);
\draw[gena] (nAb) -- (nbab);
\draw[genb] (nAb) -- (nA);
\draw[gena] (nbA) -- (nbAA);
\draw[genb] (nbA) -- (naba);
\draw[gena] (nAA) -- (naa);
\draw[genb] (nAA) -- (nAAb);
\draw[gena] (nbaa) -- (nba);
\draw[genb] (nbaa) -- (nbaab);
\draw[gena] (naba) -- (nab);
\draw[genb] (naba) -- (nbA);
\draw[gena] (nAba) -- (nAb);
\draw[genb] (nAba) -- (nAbab);
\draw[gena] (naab) -- (naabA);
\draw[genb] (naab) -- (naa);
\draw[gena] (nbab) -- (nbabA);
\draw[genb] (nbab) -- (nba);
\draw[gena] (nAAb) -- (nAbab);
\draw[genb] (nAAb) -- (nAA);
\draw[gena] (nabA) -- (nabAA);
\draw[genb] (nabA) -- (naaba);
\draw[gena] (nbAA) -- (nbaa);
\draw[genb] (nbAA) -- (nbAAb);
\draw[gena] (nabaa) -- (naba);
\draw[genb] (nabaa) -- (nabaab);
\draw[gena] (nAbaa) -- (nAba);
\draw[genb] (nAbaa) -- (nAbaab);
\draw[gena] (naaba) -- (naab);
\draw[genb] (naaba) -- (nabA);
\draw[gena] (nAAba) -- (nAAb);
\draw[genb] (nAAba) -- (naabA);
\draw[gena] (nbaab) -- (nbaabA);
\draw[genb] (nbaab) -- (nbaa);
\draw[gena] (nAbab) -- (nAbabA);
\draw[genb] (nAbab) -- (nAba);
\draw[gena] (nbAAb) -- (nabaab);
\draw[genb] (nbAAb) -- (nbAA);
\draw[gena] (naabA) -- (naabAA);
\draw[genb] (naabA) -- (nAAba);
\draw[gena] (nbabA) -- (nAbaa);
\draw[genb] (nbabA) -- (nbaaba);
\draw[gena] (nabAA) -- (nabaa);
\draw[genb] (nabAA) -- (nabAAb);
\draw[gena] (naabaa) -- (naaba);
\draw[genb] (naabaa) -- (naabaab);
\draw[gena] (nAAbaa) -- (nAAba);
\draw[genb] (nAAbaa) -- (nAAbaab);
\draw[gena] (nbaaba) -- (nbaab);
\draw[genb] (nbaaba) -- (nbabA);
\draw[gena] (nbAAba) -- (nbAAb);
\draw[genb] (nbAAba) -- (nbaabA);
\draw[gena] (nabaab) -- (nabaabA);
\draw[genb] (nabaab) -- (nabaa);
\draw[gena] (nAbaab) -- (nAbaabA);
\draw[genb] (nAbaab) -- (nAbaa);
\draw[gena] (nabAAb) -- (naabaab);
\draw[genb] (nabAAb) -- (nabAA);
\draw[gena] (nbaabA) -- (nbaabAA);
\draw[genb] (nbaabA) -- (nbAAba);
\draw[gena] (nAbabA) -- (nAAbaa);
\draw[genb] (nAbabA) -- (nAbaaba);
\draw[gena] (naabAA) -- (naabaa);
\draw[genb] (naabAA) -- (naabAAb);
\draw[gena] (nbaabaa) -- (nbaaba);
\draw[genb] (nbaabaa) -- (nAbaabA);
\draw[gena] (nbAAbaa) -- (nbAAba);
\draw[genb] (nbAAbaa) -- (nbAAbaab);
\draw[gena] (nAbaaba) -- (nAbaab);
\draw[genb] (nAbaaba) -- (nAbabA);
\draw[gena] (nabAAba) -- (nabAAb);
\draw[genb] (nabAAba) -- (nabaabA);
\draw[gena] (naabaab) -- (naabaabA);
\draw[genb] (naabaab) -- (naabaa);
\draw[gena] (nAAbaab) -- (nAAbaabA);
\draw[genb] (nAAbaab) -- (nAAbaa);
\draw[gena] (naabAAb) -- (nAAbaab);
\draw[genb] (naabAAb) -- (naabAA);
\draw[gena] (nabaabA) -- (nbAAbaa);
\draw[genb] (nabaabA) -- (nabAAba);
\draw[gena] (nAbaabA) -- (nAbaabAA);
\draw[genb] (nAbaabA) -- (nbaabaa);
\draw[gena] (nbaabAA) -- (nbaabaa);
\draw[genb] (nbaabAA) -- (nbaabAAb);
\draw[gena] (nAbaabaa) -- (nAbaaba);
\draw[genb] (nAbaabaa) -- (nAAbaabA);
\draw[gena] (nabAAbaa) -- (nabAAba);
\draw[genb] (nabAAbaa) -- (nabAAbaab);
\draw[gena] (naabAAba) -- (naabAAb);
\draw[genb] (naabAAba) -- (naabaabA);
\draw[gena] (nbAAbaab) -- (nabAAbaab);
\draw[genb] (nbAAbaab) -- (nbAAbaa);
\draw[gena] (nbaabAAb) -- (nbAAbaab);
\draw[genb] (nbaabAAb) -- (nbaabAA);
\draw[gena] (naabaabA) -- (nabAAbaa);
\draw[genb] (naabaabA) -- (naabAAba);
\draw[gena] (nAAbaabA) -- (naabAAbaa);
\draw[genb] (nAAbaabA) -- (nAbaabaa);
\draw[gena] (nAbaabAA) -- (nAbaabaa);
\draw[genb] (nAbaabAA) -- (nbaabAAba);
\draw[gena] (naabAAbaa) -- (naabAAba);
\draw[genb] (naabAAbaa) -- (nbaabAAbaa);
\draw[gena] (nbaabAAba) -- (nbaabAAb);
\draw[genb] (nbaabAAba) -- (nAbaabAA);
\draw[gena] (nabAAbaab) -- (nbaabAAbaa);
\draw[genb] (nabAAbaab) -- (nabAAbaa);
\draw[gena] (nbaabAAbaa) -- (nbaabAAba);
\draw[genb] (nbaabAAbaa) -- (naabAAbaa);
\end{tikzpicture}
\end{sidecaption}
\end{figure}
\section{Subgroups of free groups}
\label{sec:subgroups-free}
We now study subgroups of free groups.\marginnote{%
Our discussion follows the work of
\citeauthor{Swan2022}\footnotemark{}.}\footcitetext{Swan2022}
We'll eventually prove the Nielsen--Schreier theorem,
which states that a finite index subgroup $H$ of a free group $\FG_S$ is itself a free group.
Furthermore, when $S$ is finite, the set of free generators of $H$ is itself finite.
Recall from~\cref{def:set-of-subgroups} that a subgroup is (or can be represented by)
a transitive $G$-set $X : \BG \to \Set$ along with an element of $X(\sh_G)$.
\begin{definition}\label{def:finite-index}
A subgroup of a group $G$ has \emph{finite index} $m$ if the underlying
transitive $G$-set, $X : \BG \to \Set$ is a family of finite sets of cardinality $m$.
\end{definition}
The is the case, of course, if and only if the set acted on, $X(\sh_G)$, is finite
of cardinality $m$.
Notice that the definition doesn't depend on the chosen element of $X(\sh_G)$,
so applies equally to all conjugacy classes of the subgroup.
Recall also that the classifying type of the subgroup is the total type $\sum_{t:\BG}X(t)$ (which is pointed via the chosen point of $X(\sh_G)$).
We'll use the Flattening~\cref{def:graph-quotient-flattening} to analyze
this in case where $G$ is the free group on a set $S$, $\FG_S$,
so we need to show that the quotient of the resulting graph
is equivalent to $\bn 1/T$ for some set $T$.
We do this by finding a ``spanning tree'' in the graph.
\begin{definition}
A graph $(V,E)$ is \emph{connected}\index{connected!graph} if $V/E$ is a connected type
and it's a \emph{tree} if $V/E$ is contractible.
\end{definition}
\begin{definition}
A \emph{subgraph} of a graph $(V,E)$ consists of a subtype $h : U \hookrightarrow V$
of the vertices along with, for every pair of vertices $v,w$ in $U$,
a subtype $D(v,w)$ of the edges $E(v,w)$.
\end{definition}
If we represent graphs by source and target maps, then this amounts to embeddings
$h : U \hookrightarrow V$ and $k : D \hookrightarrow E$ along with witnesses that the
following squares commute:
\[
\begin{tikzcd}
D \ar[r,hook,"k"]\ar[d,"s"'] & E \ar[d,"s"] \\
U \ar[r,hook,"h"'] & V
\end{tikzcd}\quad
\begin{tikzcd}
D \ar[r,hook,"k"]\ar[d,"t"'] & E \ar[d,"t"] \\
U \ar[r,hook,"h"'] & V
\end{tikzcd}
\]
\begin{definition}
A \emph{spanning tree} in a graph $(V,E)$ is a subgraph $(U,D)$
such that $(U,D)$ is a tree, and the embedding of the vertices
$U \hookrightarrow V$ is an equivalence.
\end{definition}
Equivalently, it's given by subtypes of the edges (leaving the vertices alone)
such that the underlying graph is a tree.
Very often we'll require that the edge embeddings are decidable,
\ie we can decide whether a given edge $e : E(v,w)$ is part of the tree.
\begin{marginfigure}
\begin{tikzpicture}
\draw (-.25,0.9) ellipse (.55 and 1.2);
\node (X) at (0,2.4) {$V_0$};
\draw (1.2,1.1) ellipse (.7 and 1);
\node (Y) at (1,2.3) {$V_1$};
\node[dot,label=below:$v_0$] (x) at (-.1,0.4) {};
\node[dot,label=above:$v_1$] (y) at (1.6,1.3) {};
\node[dot,label=below:$u_0$] (s) at (-.1,1.4) {};
\node[dot,label=below:$u_1$] (t) at (1.0,1.3) {};
\draw[casblue,dotted,<->] (s) -- (t) node[midway,label=above:$e$] {};
\draw[dashed] (0.5,1.1) ellipse (1.5 and 1.9);
\node (XY) at (-0.75,3.05) {$V_0 \amalg V_1$};
\end{tikzpicture}
\caption{A connected graph with a crossing edge}
\label{fig:crossing-edge}
\end{marginfigure}
\begin{lemma}\label{lem:crossing-edge}
Suppose we have a connected graph $(V,E)$ whose type of vertices
decomposes as a binary sum $V \equivto V_0 \amalg V_1$
and we have $v_0:V_0$ and $v_1:V_1$.
Then there merely exists an edge $e$ either with source in $V_0$ and target in $V_1$
or the other way round.
\end{lemma}
The situation is illustrated in~\cref{fig:crossing-edge}, where we assume
there is an edge relation on the binary sum that gives a connected graph,
and hence there must be a ``crossing edge'' $e$, going either from $V_0$ to $V_1$
or the other way.
\begin{proof}
We may assume $V \jdeq V_0 \amalg V_1$ by path induction.
The idea is then to define a family of propositions $P : V/E \to \Prop$
that, on one hand is trivially true over $V_0$, and on the other hand
expresses our desired goal, the existence of a ``crossing edge'', over $V_1$.
We now define $P(z)$, for $z:V/E$,
by the induction principle for the graph quotient $V/E$.
We set $P([\inl v]) \defeq \true$ for $v : V_0$ and
\[
P([\inr v]) \defeq \Trunc*{\sum_{u_0:V_0}\sum_{u_1:V_1}
\bigl(E(u_0,u_1) \amalg E(u_1,u_0)\bigr)}
\]
for $v : V_1$.
We must then prove that the propositions $P([v])$ and $P([v'])$ are equivalent
whenever there's an edge from $v$ to $v'$.
This is the case by definition when $v,v'$ lie in the same summand,
and it's also the case when they lie in different summands, since then
we get a witness for the truth over $V_1$.
Since $V/E$ is connected, $P$ must have a constant truth value,
and since $P([\inl{v_0}])\jdeq\true$, every $P(z)$ is true.
Hence also $P([\inr{v_1}])$ is true, which is exactly what we wanted.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}\label{lem:spanning-tree-step}
Fix a connected graph $(V,E)$ where $V$ has decidable equality and $E$ is a family of sets.
For any subgraph $(U,D)$, where the embedding $U\hookrightarrow V$ is decidable,
and with vertices $u \in U$ and $v \in V \setminus U$,
there merely exists\footnote{%
Keep in mind that subgraphs consist not only of the vertices and edges,
but also of the corresponding embeddings into the supergraph.
It's for the sake of these that we only prove mere existence.\\
\begin{tikzcd}[sep=small,ampersand replacement=\&]
D \ar[r,hook]\ar[d,shift left]\ar[d,shift right] \&
D\amalg\bn 1 \ar[r,hook]\ar[d,shift left]\ar[d,shift right] \&
E\ar[d,shift left]\ar[d,shift right] \\
U \ar[r,hook]\ar[d] \&
U\amalg\bn 1 \ar[r,hook]\ar[d] \&
V \ar[d] \\
U/D \ar[r,"\equiv"] \&
(U\amalg\bn 1)/(D\amalg\bn 1)\ar[r] \&
V/E
\end{tikzcd}}
a larger subgraph with exactly one more vertex and one more edge,
$(U\amalg\bn 1, D\amalg\bn 1)$ such that the induced map on graph quotients
$U/D \to (U\amalg\bn 1)/(D\amalg\bn 1)$ is an equivalence.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Since the embedding $U\hookrightarrow V$ is decidable,
we can write $V$ as the binary sum $U \amalg (V\setminus U)$.
Apply~\cref{lem:crossing-edge} to find a ``crossing edge'' $e$,
and form the new subgraph $(U\amalg\bn 1, D\amalg\bn 1)$ by adding
the incident vertex not in $U$ as well as the edge $e$ itself.
The embedding $U\amalg\bn 1 \to V$ is still decidable, since $V$ has decidable equality.
Finally, we have
\[
(U\amalg\bn 1) / (D\amalg\bn 1) \equivto \bigl((U\amalg\bn 1)/\bn 1\bigr)/D
\equivto U/D,
\]
using~\cref{xca:graph-quotient-in-steps,xca:graph-quotient-whisker}, as desired.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}\label{lem:spanning-tree}
Let $(V,E)$ be a connected graph where $V$ is an $n$-element set,
and $E$ is a family of decidable sets. Then the graph merely has a spanning tree
with exactly $n-1$ edges.
\end{lemma}
\begin{marginfigure}
\begin{tikzpicture}
\node[dot] (v1) at (0,0) {};
\node[dot] (v2) at (1,0) {};
\node[dot] (v3) at (-.4,1) {};
\node[dot] (v4) at (.7,.9) {};
\node[dot] (v5) at (.5,1.8) {};
\node[dot] (v6) at (1.5,1.6) {};
\draw[->,casred] (v1) -- (v2);
\draw[->,casred] (v1) to[out=135,in=270] (v3);
\draw[->,casred] (v3) -- (v4);
\draw[->] (v4) -- (v2);
\draw[->,casred] (v6) to[out=200,in=80] (v3);
\draw[->] (v2) to[out=45,in=270] (v6);
\draw[->] (v6) -- (v4);
\draw[->,casred] (v6) to[out=90,in=45] (v5);
\end{tikzpicture}
\caption{A connected graph on $6$ vertices with a spanning tree indicated
in~\textcolor{casred}{red}.}
\label{fig:spanning-tree-example}
\end{marginfigure}
\begin{proof}
We show by induction on $k$, with $1\le k\le n$, that there merely exists
a subgraph $(U,D)$ with $k$ vertices, $k-1$ edges, and $U/D$ contractible,
\ie the graph $(U,D)$ is a tree.
For $k\jdeq 1$, we use that $V/E$ is connected to get that $V$ merely has a vertex $v$.
This then defines the desired subgraph on one vertex with no edges,
and this is clearly a tree.
Suppose we have such a desired subgraph $(U,D)$
with $k$ vertices and $k-1$ edges and $k<n$.
Since $V$ is finite, there exists vertices $u \in U$ and $v \in V \setminus U$.
Now apply~\cref{lem:spanning-tree-step} to get the next subgraph.
Finally, the subgraph $(U,D)$ with $n$ vertices and $n-1$ edges gives
the desired spanning tree, and any embedding of an $n$-element set
in another $n$-element set is an equivalence.\footnote{%
Assuming the Axiom of Choice, we can show the mere existence of a spanning tree
in any graph $(V,E)$ with a sets of vertices and edges.
See the above work by~\citeauthor{Swan2022}.}
\end{proof}
\begin{theorem}[Nielsen--Schreier Theorem]
Suppose that $S$ is a set with decidable equality and
$X : \BFG_S \to \Set$ defines a (conjugacy class of a)
finite index subgroup of $\FG_S$.
Then $\sum_{z:\BFG_S}X(z)$ is merely equivalent to $\BFG_T$ for some set $T$.
Moreover, if $S$ is a finite set of cardinality $n$ and the subgroup has index $m$,
then $T$ can be taken to be a finite set of cardinality $m(n-1)+1$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
By the Flattening~\cref{def:graph-quotient-flattening},
we have an equivalence $\flt:\bigl(\sum_{z:\BFG_S}X(z)\bigr) \equivto V/E$,
with $V\defeq X(\base)$ and $E(x,y) \defeq \sum_{s:S}(\pathover{x}{X}{\Sloop_s}{y})$.
By the finite index assumption, $V$ is a finite set,
say, of cardinality $m>0$,
and since both $S$ and $X(\base)$ are decidable, so is $E$.
By~\cref{lem:spanning-tree}, the graph $(V,E)$ merely contains
a spanning tree with
$m-1$ edges $E_0$, and complementary edge set $E_1$. Hence,
using \cref{xca:graph-quotient-in-steps}, we have a chain of equivalences:
\[
V/E \equivto (V/E_0)/E_1
\equivto \bn 1/E_1 \equivto \BFG_{E_1}
\]
This establishes the first claim with $T \defeq E_1$.
If, furthermore, $S$ has cardinality $n$, then the graph $(V,E)$
has $mn$ edges, as there are precisely $n$ outgoing edges from each vertex.
Since $E_0$ has $m-1$ edges,
that leaves $mn - (m-1) = mn-m+1 = m(n-1)+1$ edges in $E_1$, as desired.
\end{proof}
(This also has an automata theoretic proof, see below.)
\section{Intersecting subgroups}
\label{sec:intersecting-subgroups}
Stallings folding\footcite{Stallings1991}.
\begin{theorem}
Let $H$ be a finitely generated subgroup of $F(S)$ and let $u\in\tilde S^*$
be a reduced word. Then $u$ represents an element of $H$ if and only if
$u$ is recognized by the Stallings automaton $\mathcal{S}(H)$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{theorem}
Let $H$ be a finitely generated subgroup of $F(S)$.
Then $H$ has finite index if and only if $\mathcal{S}(H)$ is total.
Furthermore, in this case the index equals the number of vertices of
$\mathcal{S}(H)$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{corollary}
If $H$ has index $n$ in $F(S)$, then $\casop{\constant{rk}} H = 1 + n(\casop{\constant{card}} S-1)$.
\end{corollary}
\begin{theorem}\label{thm:howson-neumann}
Suppose $H_1,H_2$ are two subgroups of $F$ with finite indices $h_1,h_2$.
Then the intersection $H_1\cap H_2$ has finite index at most $h_1h_2$.
\end{theorem}
\marginnote{The qualitative part of \cref{thm:howson-neumann}
is known as \emph{Howson's theorem}, while the inequality
is known as \emph{Hanna Neumann's inequality}.
Hanna's son, Walter Neumann, conjectured that the $2$ could be removed,
and this was later proved independently by Joel Friedman
and Igor Mineyev.}
\section{Connections with automata (*)}
($S$ is still a fixed finite set.)
Let $\iota : F(S) \to \tilde S^*$ map an element of the free group to the corresponding reduced word.
The kernel of $\iota$ is the \emph{2-sided Dyck language} $\mathcal D_S$.
The following theorem is due to Benois.
\begin{theorem}
A subset $X$ of $F(S)$ is rational if and only if
$\iota(X)\subseteq \tilde S^*$ is a regular language.
\end{theorem}
\begin{lemma}
Let $\rho : \tilde S^* \to \tilde S^*$ map a word to its reduction.
Then $\rho$ maps regular languages to regular languages.
\end{lemma}
The following is due to Sénizergues:
\begin{theorem}
A rational subset of $F(S)$ is either disjunctive or recognizable.
\end{theorem}
Given a surjective monoid homomorphism $\alpha : S^* \to G$,
we define the corresponding \emph{matched homomorphism} $\tilde\alpha : \tilde S^* \to G$ by $(\tilde\alpha(a^{-1}) \defeq \alpha(a)^{-1}$.
\begin{theorem}[?]
Consider a f.g.\ group $G$ with a surjective homomorphism
$\alpha : F(S) \to G$. A subset $X$ of $G$ is recognisable by a finite $G$-action
if and only if $\tilde\alpha^{-1}(X) \subseteq \tilde S^*$ is rational (i.e., regular).
\end{theorem}
\begin{theorem}[Chomsky--Schützenberger]
A language $L \subseteq T^*$ is context-free if and only if
$L = h(R \cap D_S)$ for some finite $S$,
where $h : T^* \to \tilde S^*$ is a homomorphism,
$R \subseteq \tilde S^*$ is a regular language, and
$D_S$ is the Dyck language for $S$.\footnote{%
References TODO. The theorem is also true if we replace $D_S$
by its one-sided variant, but in this case it reduces to
the well-known equivalence between context-free languages
and languages recognizable by pushdown automata.}
\end{theorem}
\begin{theorem}[Muller--Schupp, ?]
Suppose $\tilde\alpha : \tilde S^* \to G$ is a surjective matched homomorphism
onto a group $G$. Then $G$ is virtually free (i.e., $G$ has a normal free subgroup of finite index) if and only if $\ker(\tilde\alpha)$ is a context-free language.
\end{theorem}
\begin{theorem}
\end{theorem}
The Stallings automaton is an \emph{inverse automaton}:
it's deterministic,
and there's an edge $(p,a,q)$ if and only if there's one $(q,A,p)$.
We can always think of the latter as the \emph{reverse} edge.
(It's then also deterministic in the reverse direction.)
Two vertices $p,q$ get identified in the Stallings graph/automaton
if and only if there is a run from $p$ to $q$ with a word $w$
whose reduction is $1$. (So a word like $aAAaBBbb$.)
\begin{theorem}
Let $X \subseteq F(S)$. Then $Y$ is a coset $Hw$ with $H$
a finitely generated subgroup,
if and only if
there is a finite state inverse automaton whose language (after reduction)
is $Y$.
\end{theorem}
\begin{corollary}
The generalized word problem in $F(S)$ is solvable:
Given a finitely generated subgroup $H$, and a word $u : \tilde S^*$,
we can decide whether $u$ represents an element of $H$.
\end{corollary}
\marginnote{%
The Stallings automaton for $H$ can be constructed in time
$O(n \log^*n)$, where $n$ is the sum of the lengths of the generators for $H$.
[Cite: Touikan: A fast algorithm for Stallings' folding process.]
Once this has been constructed, we can solve membership in $H$ in linear time.}
As above, we get a basis for $H$ as a free group from a spanning tree in
$\mathcal{S}(H)$.
\begin{theorem}
We can decide whether two f.g.\ subgroups of $F(S)$ are conjugate.
Moreover, a f.g.\ subgroup $H$ is normal if and only if $\mathcal{S}(H)$
is vertex-transitive.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
$G,H$ are conjugate of and only if their cores are equal.
\end{proof}
There are other connections between group theory and language theory:
\begin{theorem}[Anisimov and Seifert]
A subgroup $H$ of $G$ is rational if and only if $H$ is finitely generated.
\end{theorem}
\begin{theorem}
A subgroup $H$ of $G$ is recognizable if and only if it has finite index.
\end{theorem}
%%% Local Variables:
%%% mode: latex
%%% fill-column: 144
%%% TeX-master: "book"
%%% End: