-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 1
/
HoareAsLogic.v
278 lines (237 loc) · 9.42 KB
/
HoareAsLogic.v
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
(** * HoareAsLogic: Hoare Logic as a Logic *)
(* $Date: 2013-07-17 16:19:11 -0400 (Wed, 17 Jul 2013) $ *)
Require Export Hoare.
(** The presentation of Hoare logic in chapter [Hoare] could be
described as "model-theoretic": the proof rules for each of the
constructors were presented as _theorems_ about the evaluation
behavior of programs, and proofs of program correctness (validity
of Hoare triples) were constructed by combining these theorems
directly in Coq.
Another way of presenting Hoare logic is to define a completely
separate proof system -- a set of axioms and inference rules that
talk about commands, Hoare triples, etc. -- and then say that a
proof of a Hoare triple is a valid derivation in _that_ logic. We
can do this by giving an inductive definition of _valid
derivations_ in this new logic. *)
Inductive hoare_proof : Assertion -> com -> Assertion -> Type :=
| H_Skip : forall P,
hoare_proof P (SKIP) P
| H_Asgn : forall Q V a,
hoare_proof (assn_sub V a Q) (V ::= a) Q
| H_Seq : forall P c Q d R,
hoare_proof P c Q -> hoare_proof Q d R -> hoare_proof P (c;;d) R
| H_If : forall P Q b c1 c2,
hoare_proof (fun st => P st /\ bassn b st) c1 Q ->
hoare_proof (fun st => P st /\ ~(bassn b st)) c2 Q ->
hoare_proof P (IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) Q
| H_While : forall P b c,
hoare_proof (fun st => P st /\ bassn b st) c P ->
hoare_proof P (WHILE b DO c END) (fun st => P st /\ ~ (bassn b st))
| H_Consequence : forall (P Q P' Q' : Assertion) c,
hoare_proof P' c Q' ->
(forall st, P st -> P' st) ->
(forall st, Q' st -> Q st) ->
hoare_proof P c Q.
Tactic Notation "hoare_proof_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "H_Skip" | Case_aux c "H_Asgn" | Case_aux c "H_Seq"
| Case_aux c "H_If" | Case_aux c "H_While" | Case_aux c "H_Consequence" ].
(** We don't need to include axioms corresponding to [hoare_consequence_pre]
or [hoare_consequence_post], because these can be proven easily
from [H_Consequence]. *)
Lemma H_Consequence_pre : forall (P Q P': Assertion) c,
hoare_proof P' c Q ->
(forall st, P st -> P' st) ->
hoare_proof P c Q.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Lemma H_Consequence_post : forall (P Q Q' : Assertion) c,
hoare_proof P c Q' ->
(forall st, Q' st -> Q st) ->
hoare_proof P c Q.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** Now, for example, let's construct a proof object representing a
derivation for the hoare triple
{{assn_sub X (X+1) (assn_sub X (X+2) (X=3))}} X::=X+1;; X::=X+2 {{X=3}}.
We can use Coq's tactics to help us construct the proof object. *)
Example sample_proof
: hoare_proof
(assn_sub X (APlus (AId X) (ANum 1))
(assn_sub X (APlus (AId X) (ANum 2))
(fun st => st X = 3) ))
(X ::= APlus (AId X) (ANum 1);; (X ::= APlus (AId X) (ANum 2)))
(fun st => st X = 3).
Proof.
eapply H_Seq; apply H_Asgn.
Qed.
(*
Print sample_proof.
====>
H_Seq
(assn_sub X (APlus (AId X) (ANum 1))
(assn_sub X (APlus (AId X) (ANum 2)) (fun st : state => st X = VNat 3)))
(X ::= APlus (AId X) (ANum 1))
(assn_sub X (APlus (AId X) (ANum 2)) (fun st : state => st X = VNat 3))
(X ::= APlus (AId X) (ANum 2)) (fun st : state => st X = VNat 3)
(H_Asgn
(assn_sub X (APlus (AId X) (ANum 2)) (fun st : state => st X = VNat 3))
X (APlus (AId X) (ANum 1)))
(H_Asgn (fun st : state => st X = VNat 3) X (APlus (AId X) (ANum 2)))
*)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars (hoare_proof_sound) *)
(** Prove that such proof objects represent true claims. *)
Theorem hoare_proof_sound : forall P c Q,
hoare_proof P c Q -> {{P}} c {{Q}}.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** We can also use Coq's reasoning facilities to prove metatheorems
about Hoare Logic. For example, here are the analogs of two
theorems we saw in chapter [Hoare] -- this time expressed in terms
of the syntax of Hoare Logic derivations (provability) rather than
directly in terms of the semantics of Hoare triples.
The first one says that, for every [P] and [c], the assertion
[{{P}} c {{True}}] is _provable_ in Hoare Logic. Note that the
proof is more complex than the semantic proof in [Hoare]: we
actually need to perform an induction over the structure of the
command [c]. *)
Theorem H_Post_True_deriv:
forall c P, hoare_proof P c (fun _ => True).
Proof.
intro c.
com_cases (induction c) Case; intro P.
Case "SKIP".
eapply H_Consequence.
apply H_Skip.
intros. apply H.
(* Proof of True *)
intros. apply I.
Case "::=".
eapply H_Consequence_pre.
apply H_Asgn.
intros. apply I.
Case ";;".
eapply H_Consequence_pre.
eapply H_Seq.
apply (IHc1 (fun _ => True)).
apply IHc2.
intros. apply I.
Case "IFB".
apply H_Consequence_pre with (fun _ => True).
apply H_If.
apply IHc1.
apply IHc2.
intros. apply I.
Case "WHILE".
eapply H_Consequence.
eapply H_While.
eapply IHc.
intros; apply I.
intros; apply I.
Qed.
(** Similarly, we can show that [{{False}} c {{Q}}] is provable for
any [c] and [Q]. *)
Lemma False_and_P_imp: forall P Q,
False /\ P -> Q.
Proof.
intros P Q [CONTRA HP].
destruct CONTRA.
Qed.
Tactic Notation "pre_false_helper" constr(CONSTR) :=
eapply H_Consequence_pre;
[eapply CONSTR | intros ? CONTRA; destruct CONTRA].
Theorem H_Pre_False_deriv:
forall c Q, hoare_proof (fun _ => False) c Q.
Proof.
intros c.
com_cases (induction c) Case; intro Q.
Case "SKIP". pre_false_helper H_Skip.
Case "::=". pre_false_helper H_Asgn.
Case ";;". pre_false_helper H_Seq. apply IHc1. apply IHc2.
Case "IFB".
apply H_If; eapply H_Consequence_pre.
apply IHc1. intro. eapply False_and_P_imp.
apply IHc2. intro. eapply False_and_P_imp.
Case "WHILE".
eapply H_Consequence_post.
eapply H_While.
eapply H_Consequence_pre.
apply IHc.
intro. eapply False_and_P_imp.
intro. simpl. eapply False_and_P_imp.
Qed.
(** As a last step, we can show that the set of [hoare_proof] axioms is
sufficient to prove any true fact about (partial) correctness.
More precisely, any semantic Hoare triple that we can prove can
also be proved from these axioms. Such a set of axioms is said
to be _relatively complete_. *)
(** This proof is inspired by the one at
http://www.ps.uni-saarland.de/courses/sem-ws11/script/Hoare.html
*)
(** To prove this fact, we'll need to invent some intermediate
assertions using a technical device known as _weakest preconditions_.
Given a command [c] and a desired postcondition assertion [Q],
the weakest precondition [wp c Q] is an assertion [P] such that
[{{P}} c {{Q}}] holds, and moreover, for any other assertion [P'],
if [{{P'}} c {{Q}}] holds then [P' -> P]. We can more directly
define this as follows: *)
Definition wp (c:com) (Q:Assertion) : Assertion :=
fun s => forall s', c / s || s' -> Q s'.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (wp_is_precondition) *)
Lemma wp_is_precondition: forall c Q,
{{wp c Q}} c {{Q}}.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (wp_is_weakest) *)
Lemma wp_is_weakest: forall c Q P',
{{P'}} c {{Q}} -> forall st, P' st -> wp c Q st.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** The following utility lemma will also be useful. *)
Lemma bassn_eval_false : forall b st, ~ bassn b st -> beval st b = false.
Proof.
intros b st H. unfold bassn in H. destruct (beval st b).
exfalso. apply H. reflexivity.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars (hoare_proof_complete) *)
(** Complete the proof of the theorem. *)
Theorem hoare_proof_complete: forall P c Q,
{{P}} c {{Q}} -> hoare_proof P c Q.
Proof.
intros P c. generalize dependent P.
com_cases (induction c) Case; intros P Q HT.
Case "SKIP".
eapply H_Consequence.
eapply H_Skip.
intros. eassumption.
intro st. apply HT. apply E_Skip.
Case "::=".
eapply H_Consequence.
eapply H_Asgn.
intro st. apply HT. econstructor. reflexivity.
intros; assumption.
Case ";;".
apply H_Seq with (wp c2 Q).
eapply IHc1.
intros st st' E1 H. unfold wp. intros st'' E2.
eapply HT. econstructor; eassumption. assumption.
eapply IHc2. intros st st' E1 H. apply H; assumption.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** Finally, we might hope that our axiomatic Hoare logic is _decidable_;
that is, that there is an (terminating) algorithm (a _decision procedure_)
that can determine whether or not a given Hoare triple is valid (derivable).
But such a decision procedure cannot exist!
Consider the triple [{{True}} c {{False}}]. This triple is valid
if and only if [c] is non-terminating. So any algorithm that could
determine validity of arbitrary triples could solve the Halting Problem.
Similarly, the triple [{{True} SKIP {{P}}] is valid if and only if
[forall s, P s] is valid, where [P] is an arbitrary assertion of Coq's
logic. But it is known that there can be no decision procedure for
this logic.
*)
(** Overall, this axiomatic style of presentation gives a clearer picture of what it
means to "give a proof in Hoare logic." However, it is not
entirely satisfactory from the point of view of writing down such
proofs in practice: it is quite verbose. The section of chapter
[Hoare2] on formalizing decorated programs shows how we can do even
better. *)